Plato, part 2

SONY DSCMosaic believed to depict Plato’s Academy.
Found in the ruins of Pompeii.

(Continued from part 1.)

Plato never wrote out a full statement of his philosophy in any one place, and the literary aspect of his work makes it difficult to identify what that philosophy even was. In that respect, Losev did a great service just by concisely explaining it. I will therefore turn the floor over to him:

Does any one thing differ, in any way, from any other thing, or are all things identical? If there is no difference between a certain thing and any other thing, then we cannot ascribe any specific characteristic or quality to it, and then it is impossible to speak of our understanding of that thing. If we know what a certain thing is, then to us it is something, and therefore it is something specific, and therefore it can be described as the confluence of various qualities. First, a table is made of wood. Second, a table is a device used for various household activities, such as eating, or reading and writing, or the purposeful organization and placement of different objects. So, the combination of all of these natural properties is the idea of the table… In other words, the idea of a thing is something that is essentially and vitally necessary for us to be able to understand that thing, to interact with it, to use it, to create it, to alter it and to direct it towards various purposes.
In that sense, any thing and, in general, anything that exists in the world, has its own idea. If there are no ideas, then there is no way to differentiate between things, and thus all of reality turns into senseless and unknowable darkness. One can agree that Plato’s writing is sometimes unclear, sometimes quite difficult, and sometimes even incorrect. Sometimes he ascribes a completely different meaning to ideas — not just that they are the combination of essential properties of different things, but also that each idea is the purpose of a thing, and also that it is the means of understanding the thing’s existence… But, in any case, anyone should be able to understand that the idea of a thing is its meaningful and essential aspect, and this notion also plays a leading role in Plato’s teaching about ideas.
Now, if we have mastered this notion, we can go further. Anyone will ask: what is the precise relationship between the idea of a thing, understood in this way, and the thing itself?
A table can be painted, a table can be made big or small, a table can be decorated or repaired, a table can be broken into pieces and these pieces can be burned, thus turning the entire table into ash. But can all of this also be done with the idea of the table? Can the idea of the table be made light or dark, red or brown, heavy or light? Can the idea of the table be smelled or touched? The table itself can, but what about its idea? Can the idea of the table be chopped into pieces or turned into ash? Of course, water can freeze and boil; but can the idea of water freeze and boil, or is it unable to freeze or boil?
From this very simple observation of the most ordinary, the most commonplace and routine things…there follows the absolute impossibility of ascribing material qualities to ideas. The idea of a thing is related only to that thing and nothing else, but surprisingly, this idea of the thing, which reveals all of its essential qualities and properties, itself is not something material, and it is meaningless to ascribe anything material to it.”

(Losev, 108-111)

These simple, deliberately crude examples spell out a deep insight into the nature of human reason, which seems more difficult to grasp the more one thinks about it. We are able to interact with the material world through generalization. When you draw a circle in the sand, you know that you are looking at a circle, even though a “circle” has nothing to do with sand, and really doesn’t even have much to do with the specific shape that you drew. Nonetheless there is a certain abstract concept, a “generalized circle” which can easily be mentally connected to this specific circle and to all other circular shapes of various sizes and materials, and it is through this generalized circle that we are able to categorize and understand specific shapes. The existence of this concept, separate from the material objects that it represents — a generalized circle that encompasses all specific circles, and contains only what is truly essential for understanding them — constitutes Plato’s main contribution to human thought.

And so, if earlier we said that the idea of a thing, being the meaning of it, is essential for its existence and for our understanding of it, then now we must say…that the idea of a thing, uncovering the meaning of the thing, answering the question ‘what is this thing?’, is not at all limited to the material confluence of the material properties of the thing; rather, it is something immaterial, something incorporeal, although it points only at something material or something corporeal.
Here, however, there appears a fundamental confusion. It seems that this is really how things are: water itself may freeze, but the idea of water does not freeze. But as soon as this thesis is generalized, we immediately encounter the following quandary: how is it possible for the idea of a material thing to be immaterial? …Evidently, there now arises the question of the mutual relationship between the idea of a thing, and the thing itself, from the point of view of their origin, from the point of view of what came from what and how it comes to be.

(Losev, 112-113)

The existence of ideas has many implications. Once the “essence” of a thing has been divested from any of its material qualities, there is now a certain sense in which the thing exists forever, independently of the physical world. There is a famous philosophical example, also dating back to ancient Greece, called the Ship of Theseus: over time, every wooden part making up the ship is gradually replaced, so that eventually all of the ship’s original parts have ceased to exist, and the question is whether the ship itself still exists. Plato’s answer to the question would be that the ship is defined by its idea, rather than by its physical realization. The individual material components of the ship have no relevance to its idea; in fact, even if the physical ship were to be permanently destroyed, its idea would continue to exist, undisturbed.

This sounds like exactly the kind of detached, empty verbiage that amazes philosophy students and no one else, but in fact we implicitly rely on this notion whenever we attempt to interact with culture from the past. The world-famous Angkor Wat temple complex in Cambodia has been in ruins for much of modern history, and after it was restored by French specialists around the turn of the 20th century, it was again heavily damaged during the civil war. Many buildings in the complex look like this —

angkorwatbuilding.jpg

— and the grounds are strewn with piles of massive, eroded stones that, contrary to their abandoned appearance, have been duly catalogued and are waiting to be reassembled into other buildings. A few decades ago, many of the buildings that are standing today likewise existed only as piles of rubble. Evidently, there is an idea of Angkor Wat, which is not reducible to the buildings and stones, and whose existence was entirely uninterrupted by the repeated destruction of these material objects. The recreation of the complex is made possible and guided by this idea. It may well be that the recreation falls short of the idea — but then, as we will see, no physical representation can ever be adequate. In a certain sense, the original Angkor Wat, as it was constructed by ancient Cambodians, was just as “flawed,” as a reflection of its idea, as any other physical form in which the complex has ever existed.

Having explained the immaterial nature of ideas, Losev then delves into the debate between “materialism” (the belief that ideas are secondary to matter) and “idealism” (the opposite). He has to tread carefully in this discussion, since Soviet ideology was aggressively hyper-materialist, and Lenin treated the word “idealism” basically as a profanity. Plato’s name, of course, is first on the list of idealists throughout the ages, so Losev develops a long apologetic explanation to the effect that, “most important in Plato…is the discovery of the very existence of ideas, of their necessity for understanding all things, and of their immaterial character… Ideas in this sense are not only Plato’s discovery: without them there can be no philosophy, no science and no human understanding of any sort, even the most routine and elementary. This is the source of Plato’s greatness, and this is what forever secured for him a major role in the subsequent history of culture. We may react to this with delight or indignation, as much as we choose, but the role of Platonism in world history will not be affected one bit.” (121)

I, however, am not particularly interested in the history of the long arguments between 19th- and 20th-century ideological thinkers; in this discussion, I think it is more important to understand what “ideas” meant to Plato himself, at the time when he was writing. But this, as we said before, is not easy to do, since Plato never laid out a full statement of this system of thought. Rather, it appears in fragments throughout his dialogues, mainly those in the middle and late period. Ironically, Aristotle had to give a more systematic presentation of Plato’s ideas, for the sole purpose of criticizing them, than Plato himself had ever done:

However, the greatest difficulty comes from the question of what significance ideas have for things that can be perceived with the senses — for eternal things, or for those that come into being and perish. The issue is that ideas are not the cause of motion or any change in these things. On the other hand, ideas are also of no help in understanding all other things (they are not the essences of those things, otherwise they would have already been in them) or their existence (since they do not exist inside the things that they pertain to)…
Nonetheless, nothing else can originate from ideas in any of the usual senses of the word ‘from.’ If we say that they are a model for existence and that everything else pertains to them — then we would be speaking in idle words and poetic metaphors. Truly, is there anything that acts as a result of ideas? It is possible to resemble something without necessarily imitating a model; thus, whether or not Socrates exists, another man like Socrates might appear; and it is clear that the same could happen if some sort of eternal Socrates were to exist as well. Or there should be many models for the same thing, and thus many of its ideas… Furthermore, ideas should then be models, not only for things that can be perceived by the senses, but also for themselves…so the same thing would simultaneously be a model and an imitation.
Continuing on, we should consider it impossible for the essence of something to exist separately from the thing whose essence it is; how can ideas, if they are the essences of things, exist separately from them? And yet Plato says in ‘Phaedo’ that ideas are the causes of both the existence and the appearance of things; and yet if ideas exist, the things that pertain to them still would not have come into being if there had not been something to put them into motion.

(Metaphysics, book I, chapter 9)

aristotleAristotle, regarding the world with
the intent expression of the consummate scientist.

But if we try to follow up Aristotle’s reference to “Phaedo,” it will not be clear exactly which part he is talking about. Perhaps he meant this:

‘See what follows now,’ Socrates said, ‘and whether you will have the same opinion as I. It seems to me that, if there is something beautiful, other than beauty itself, then it will be beautiful for no other reason but that it pertains to that beauty. I say the same about everything else. Do you agree with my explanation?’
‘Yes,’ [Cebes] answered.
‘Very well,’ Socrates continued. ‘Now I do not know and do not wish to know any other wise causes, and if anyone says to me, that beauty is beautiful either because of its beautiful colour, or because of its appearance, or because of something else, then I…will say my farewells to all of them and simply — perhaps foolishly — will hold to one position, namely that beauty follows from none other than the presence, or the union, or some other participation in it by that beauty; because I have not decided precisely how this happens, but I have decided that all beautiful things are beautiful for the reason of beauty.‘”

from “Phaedo”

In other words, the beautiful quality of material things is imposed on them by the idea of beauty that, in some deliberately unspecified way, is linked with these things. Another relatively clear statement can be found in the beginning of “Parmenides”:

But tell me this: do you not agree that there exists, in and of itself, a certain idea of similarity and another, opposite idea of dissimilarity? That both you, and I, and all things that we call ‘many,’ are somehow joined to these two ideas? Further, that anything joined to similarity becomes similar for the reason, and to the extent, of its joining, and anything joined to dissimilarity likewise becomes dissimilar, and anything joined to both of them becomes both of them at the same time? And if all things are joined to both opposing ideas, and through this turn out to be similar and dissimilar among themselves, why would this be surprising? It would be strange, I think, if someone were to show that similarity in itself could become dissimilar, or dissimilarity in itself could become similar; but if I am told that something joined to both of them combines aspects of both, then, Zeno, I would not find this ridiculous at all… There is no surprise if someone will argue that I am simultaneously one and many, and, wishing to show that I am many, will point to my right and left, front and back, and top and bottom parts…and wishing to show that I am one, will say that I am joined to one because I as a person am one among the seven of us: in this way would be shown the truth of both claims.”

Socrates, in “Parmenides”

One can find more examples like these, but doing so would create a misleading impression of how Plato predominantly talks about this theory. A much more representative example, also from “Phaedo,” is the following:

‘Furthermore,’ Socrates continued, ‘the earth is very great, and we, from Phasis to the pillars of Hercules, occupy only the smallest part of it, living near the sea, like ants and frogs near the swamp. Other similar places are populated by many other inhabitants. Everywhere on earth there are many hollows of different shapes and sizes, into which the water, the clouds, and the air flow down. The real Earth stands pure in the clear sky — where the stars are. Many who have studied this subject call the sky by the name of ether, and the precipitation from it is everything that flows down into the hollows of the earth.
We do not notice the hollows, and we believe that our home is on the surface of the earth, similar to one who, living in the depth of the sea, imagines that he sees the sun and other stars through the water, and believes the sea to be the sky. Due to his sluggishness and weakness, he would never rise to the surface of the sea and see it; he would never even have the chance to hear from any witness, how much purer and more beautiful is the world that stands out of the sea in the upper levels.
This is exactly our condition: living in the hollows of the earth, we believe that we live on its surface, we believe that the air is the sky and we imagine that it is this sky in which the stars float. And all this is because our weakness and sluggishness do not permit us to rise to the limits of the air, otherwise anyone who could rise to that height or to fly up to it, having obtained wings — such a one would lift his head and, just as the fish that dive up from the sea see what is above the water, would see everything there and, if only his nature might withstand this contemplation, would finally know that there is the true sky, the true light and the true earth. Because this earth, these stones and in general everything here is damaged and corroded, like things that have been corroded by seawater, so that nothing good can grow here and, one might say, nothing is perfect, only the pitfalls, sand, endless ooze and dirt — everywhere where there is the earth, and none of this can possibly compare with what we call beauty.‘”

from “Phaedo”

Here, Plato reveals the true purpose of his theory. It is not enough that the world of ideas exists. It must also be endlessly superior to the world that we actually see. In “The Republic,” the physical world is famously compared to a cave whose denizens are unable to comprehend the true world that lies outside:

“‘After all that,’ I said, ‘you might compare our human nature, with respect to its enlightenment and ignorance, to the following condition…consider this: it is as if all mankind is in an underground dwelling, like a cave, where a wide light is cast along its entire length. From early childhood they wear chains on their legs and necks, so that they cannot move, and they see only what is directly before their eyes, because they cannot turn their heads due to these chains. They have their backs to the light that emanates from a fire, which burns far above, and between the fire and the prisoners there is a high road, closed off…by a low wall, like the curtain behind which magicians hide their assistants, when they show puppets above the curtain.’
‘This I can envision.’
‘Then imagine also that, behind this wall, other people are carrying different objects, holding them so that they can be seen over the wall; they also carry statues, and various images of living creatures, made from stone and wood. In doing so, some of them are talking and others are silent.’
‘It is a strange picture that you draw, and strange prisoners!’
‘They resemble us. First of all, do you think that, being in this condition, people are able to see anything, their own or belonging to others, except for the shadows cast by the fire on the wall of the cave in front of them?’
[…]
‘If the chains were to be removed from one of them, and he were suddenly forced to stand, turn his neck, walk down the hall and look upwards at the light, he will be in great pain to carry this out, he will hardly be able to look at those things, whose shadows he saw previously, in the bright light. And what do you think he would say when he is told that what he saw before were mere trifles, and that now, having approached existence and turned to something more genuine, he could acquire a proper view? …Do you not believe that this will perplex him greatly, and that he will think that there was much more truth in what he saw earlier, than in what he is being shown now?‘”

Socrates and Glaucon (“The Republic,” book VII)

platocave“Plato’s allegory of the cave,” Jan Saenredam, 1604.
The artist has overloaded the scene with bodies,
completely overlooking the disoriented solitude of Plato’s vision.

At this point, college freshmen everywhere wonder why this bizarre digression appears in what they were told was a political pamphlet. Their professors aren’t sure, but think that it’s probably a metaphor for the greatness of the American political system or something.

With this disquieting image, Plato has reached the point where it is also no longer enough for the world of ideas to merely be superior to the material world. In fact, the material world cannot really be called “real” at all. Everything that we perceive is nothing more than a shadow cast on the wall by a light that burns somewhere in the true world, the abstract world of ideas. Clearly, anyone capable of writing these words did not like the real world very much — and, clearly, the world of ideas meant much more to him than a toolkit for abstract thought. Plato’s descriptions of it are pure poetry, far removed from Aristotle’s sober analytical tone. There isn’t really anything philosophical about them; they have more resemblance to religious visions.

You may have heard of the term “Platonic love.” It is a direct application of Plato’s theory, laid out in the “Symposium.” After a series of increasingly exalted speeches, by various speakers, in praise of the god Eros, it is now Socrates’ turn. He frames his speech as a flashback to a time when he allegedly met the wise priestess Diotima of Mantinea, who instructed him in “the mysteries of love” as follows:

As for the most perfect and mysterious form of love, which indeed is the reason why all the lesser forms exist, I do not know if you are ready for it. But I will explain and ask you (she said), and I will not waver in my efforts, and you must follow me, if you can. One who strives for this object must begin the path toward beautiful objects properly from youth, and, if his guide teaches him well, he must first love one object and thereby give birth to wondrous speech; then he must see that beauty in any one particular body is like beauty in another, and so if it is necessary to pursue beauty in itself, then it would be madness to fail to worship it equally in all bodies. Thinking in this way, he must first learn to love all beautiful bodies, and reduce that strong love toward a single one… After this he must value beauty in souls more highly than in bodies… Thus, he will again be compelled to contemplate beauty in scholarship and law and see it as something close to himself, turning away from bodily beauty.

Diotima, via Socrates, in the “Symposium”

socratesanddiotima“Socrates and Diotima,” Franz Causig, 1810.
Diotima has not fared well in the visual arts;
this frivolous pastoral was the only depiction I could find.

In other words, physical desire, being the most “material” expression of the idea of love, is also its “least” expression. Socrates chooses to abandon it because, at some point, it becomes an obstacle blocking the way to the superior love that exists only in the world of ideas. But, more than that, love of any one person, even if it is more spiritual than physical, is still imperfect. The only proper object of love is love itself. Any other object would dilute the purity of the idea and bring it down to our world.

When studying Plato’s theory of ideas, one eventually comes to “Parmenides,” by far the most curious work in the entire Platonic corpus. This dialogue shows Socrates as a young man (quite different from most of his other appearances) in his twenties, already focused on philosophy but less sure of himself than he is elsewhere. He visits the elderly philosopher Parmenides, who, like most characters in Plato’s dialogues, was a real historical figure, quoted by Aristotle and other thinkers; unfortunately his sole philosophical work has not survived to the present day. In a brief debate with Parmenides’ student Zeno (also a real historical figure, author of Zeno’s paradoxes), Socrates lays out the theory of ideas and proposes it as a way of resolving various philosophical challenges.

parmenidesParmenides.

Parmenides hears him out favourably, expressing admiration for Socrates’ commitment to philosophy. As far as the content goes, however, Parmenides suggests that Socrates might still be too young to see the full implications of his theory, and cautions him that it might also lead to unresolvable problems:

‘But you may be sure,’ Parmenides continued, ‘that you have still not yet felt the daunting magnitude of this difficulty, if you allow each thing to have a single idea separate from itself.’
‘Why is that?’ Socrates asked.
‘For many reasons, and mainly the following one: if anyone were to argue that ideas, if they are anything like what we believe them to be, must be completely impervious to knowledge, then it would be impossible to prove that one who holds this opinion were wrong, unless perhaps the rebuttal were made by one who was most experienced and gifted, and willing to follow a multitude of arguments that were far removed from each other during the debate. In any other case, it would be impossible to change the mind of anyone insisting that ideas cannot be understood.‘”

from “Parmenides”

Parmenides then explains that, if ideas exist independently from the things that pertain to them, they can only be known through the idea of knowledge (knowledge in itself), rather than any earthly knowledge; but, since ideas do not exist inside us, we fundamentally lack the capacity for such knowledge. Thus, if the world of ideas exists, then its existence is completely closed off from the material world; not only is it impossible for us to penetrate into the world of ideas, but similarly the world of ideas lacks any mechanism for understanding us. But then it seems hard to claim that this world is superior to ours (or even relevant to ours) in any meaningful way.

This is very unusual for Plato. It is true that, sometimes, his dialogues take on surprising conversational plausibility and realism, but this is almost always a purely literary device. When it comes to actually modeling and engaging with possible counter-arguments to his work, Plato is far more frugal. In his early dialogues, Socrates’ companions may offer answers to his questions (earlier we saw Euthyphro’s attempts to define piety), but they are rarely made to argue with him in a compelling, intellectually substantive manner; Callicles’ malicious harangue in “Gorgias” is a rare exception. In Plato’s later work, the other participants do not even do this much — more typically, they reply with “Yes,” “Of course,” “No doubt,” “How could it be otherwise?” and other such empty affirmations. When they fail to challenge what seems to be an obvious logical leap by Socrates (like how, in “Meno,” he uses a slave boy’s knowledge of mathematics to extrapolate the pre-existence of souls with no attempt at rebuttal by his opponent), the effect is irritating; one feels that one is being manipulated by Plato.

In light of this general tendency, “Parmenides” is all the more striking. On one hand, Socrates is clearly serving as Plato’s mouthpiece: his position is in full agreement with what Plato wrote elsewhere. But, on the other hand, he is shown as having no rejoinder to Parmenides, who is given articulate and understandable intellectual arguments. Plato’s portrayal of Parmenides is exceedingly respectful, perhaps uniquely among Plato’s portrayals of anybody. (Well, Socrates expressed deep respect for Diotima, but she was probably a fictional character — at least, there is no independent evidence that she ever existed — whereas Parmenides was unquestionably a real person.)

And this is only about half of the dialogue. In the remaining half, Parmenides talks through a series of very abstract arguments, using a young student named Aristoteles (not the famous one) as a foil, while both Socrates and Zeno listen silently. These arguments focus on the ideas of “one,” “many,” and “other.” These notions are interpreted Platonically, as ideas, i.e., absolute abstractions that express the essence of the concepts they describe — thus, “one” is meant as “oneness,” or the “essence” of being “one.” Parmenides variously assumes that these ideas do or do not exist, and logically derives unresolvable paradoxical conclusions from each of these assumptions. I will summarize the first of these arguments:

  1. If one is one, then it is not many.
  2. If one is not many, it cannot consist of parts, and thus cannot be a “whole” (otherwise it would be made up of parts).
  3. Then, one is limitless, having no beginning or end (otherwise those would be parts of one).
  4. One cannot be in any place, because it cannot be contained inside anything, nor can anything be contained inside it.
  5. One cannot move, because it is not in any place, and one cannot change, otherwise it would no longer be one.
  6. Therefore, one can neither move nor stay still (if it stayed still, it would be somewhere).
  7. Similarly, one cannot be equal or unequal to itself: if it were unequal to itself, then it would not be one, and if it were equal to itself, it would be different from other, but only other can be different from anything.
  8. Similarly, one cannot be similar or dissimilar to anything, including itself.
  9. Similarly, one cannot become older or younger, or exist in time in any way.
  10. Therefore, one cannot exist, because it has been shown that one cannot possess any possible form of existence.
  11. If one existed in any other way, it would pertain to existence; however, existence is many, because there are many things that exist, and they all pertain in some way to existence. Therefore, if one existed, it would be many.

This goes on for a long time — the remainder of the text is a sequence of dense abstract statements that eventually lead to contradictions that, ostensibly, cannot be resolved (the final conclusion is, “if one does not exist, then nothing exists”). There is no resolution; the dialogue simply ends with no comment from Socrates. Consequently, the question left on everyone’s mind is what the point of all this was. On the surface of it, Plato just proved that his own philosophy was meaningless. By adopting the theory of ideas, one is led into an intellectual fog, from which there seems to be no escape, as soon as one attempts to analyze even a single idea.

dennishopper“Dialectic logic is, there’s only love and hate:
you either love somebody, or you hate them.”

(One of many flashes of genius in Apocalypse Now. The American psyche does not handle even small encounters with classical culture very well.)

But if Plato had to choose between logical analysis and the world of ideas, I think he would pick the latter without hesitation. It seems to me that “Parmenides” is not at all a refutation of the world of ideas — rather, it is a refutation of logic and philosophy, as imperfect tools that cannot provide a satisfactory understanding (to us who are trapped in the cave) of the perfect world that no one has ever fully seen. In “Parmenides,” Plato killed philosophy. If he had heard Aristotle’s rebuttals, he would have contemptuously kept silent: you either understand the world of ideas or you don’t, and there is nothing that mere logic is going to do about it.

Not only does Plato fail to precisely define ideas or to present them in a logically consistent manner, but this “failure” is actually a deliberate choice on his part. After all, Aristotle wrote a more consistent treatment of ideas, and Plato easily could have done the same, if he had wanted. But, in Plato’s mind, the world of ideas is better left undefined — that makes it even more perfect. At any given moment, ideas can be whatever Plato wants them to be, and the logical contradictions that arise merely serve to illustrate their supernatural greatness. In that sense, Plato is not a philosopher at all, but a poet and visionary. Only a Western academic dullard could ever think that “The Republic” was some sort of political treatise…but what does “The Republic” say, after all? Plato gives a long critique of democracy, arguing how it can turn into tyranny:

‘So, whatever democracy believes to be good and whatever it strives to achieve, that is exactly what destroys it.’
‘What is it that democracy believes to be good, in your opinion?’
‘Freedom. In a democratic state, all you can hear is how freedom is beautiful and how only such a state is worth living in for the man who is free by nature.’
‘Yes, such statements are often repeated.’
‘So, just as I was saying, such an insatiable drive toward one thing and disregard for all others will distort this system and prepare the way for the need for tyranny.’
‘How so?’
When an evil cupbearer stands at the head of a democratic state filled with the thirst for freedom, such a state becomes intoxicated with undiluted freedom beyond all measure; it punishes its officers if they are insufficiently indulgent and do not provide full freedom to everyone; it accuses them of vile oligarchical leanings.’
‘Yes, it happens exactly in that way.’
‘Those who follow the rulers are ground into the dirt, as if they were worthless slaves, but the subservient rulers and their lordly subjects are praised and respected in private and public. Is it not true that freedom will inevitably spread everywhere in such a state?’
‘How could it be otherwise?’
‘It will spread, my friend, even into private homes, and in the end insubordination will be the way even of animals…under such a system, the teacher will fear the pupils and will pander to them, and the pupils will place no value upon their teachers and mentors. In general, the young will begin to imitate adults and compete with them in words and actions, while the elders, adapting to the youth and also imitating them, will continually jest and act frivolously, so as not to seem unpleasant and authoritative.’

Socrates and Adeimantus (“The Republic,” book VIII)

In this atmosphere of devalued authority, Plato argues, there will eventually come a leader who will give the debased public what it wants. Well, it’s hard to argue with the truth; he certainly has us figured out. But after that, the scale of the discussion changes:

‘Well? Would it be an exaggeration to say that we have thoroughly investigated how democracy is transformed into tyranny, and the specifics thereof?’
‘Most thoroughly.’
‘It remains to examine the man of tyranny himself, that is, how he develops from the democratic man, what his qualities are and what sort of life he leads — one of fortune or misfortune.’
[…]
‘If the state can be divided into three classes, then in the soul of each man there are also three aspects…to each one, it seems, there corresponds a specific type of pleasure.’

Socrates and Adeimantus (“The Republic,” books VIII-IX)

What follows is a discussion of “democratic” and “tyrannical” qualities inside the soul of a single individual. The references to statesmanship now turn into metaphors, and the book closes with a long vision of the posthumous judgment of the soul, based on the individual’s ability to exercise mastery over his “tyrannical” side in life. In other words, the political content of the discussion can easily be read as a long digression, intended to create tangible images that could then figuratively stand in for the desires that tempt the individual who has chosen to dedicate himself to philosophy.

The real philosopher was Aristotle — he did exactly what Losev ascribes to Plato, namely, he developed philosophy into an analytical method for studying reality. His work demonstrates that he took an interest in everything on earth, writing about rhetoric, poetry, physics, zoology, or political science with equal depth.

Plato was interested in nothing aside from the world of ideas. Long passages in “The Republic” and “Laws,” and even earlier dialogues such as “Ion,” express deep skepticism toward the arts, and lay out narrow restrictions on what kind of poetry is acceptable and when it is acceptable to listen to it. But even with regard to his one true love, he deliberately steps back from analyzing the world of ideas directly, refusing to specify a mechanism through which ideas are joined with material objects, and preferring to fall back on the language of poetic metaphor whenever logic starts to bore him. Deep down, he is a great obscurantist — the mystery of the world of ideas is the source of its power.

schoolofathens.pngDetail from “The School of Athens,” Raphael, 1509-1511.
Plato (center-left) is pointing upward to the world of ideas;
Aristotle (center-right) is pointing to the material world.

But at the same time, while Aristotle’s philosophy was infinitely more useful to humanity and Aristotle vastly exceeded Plato as a scientist and thinker, Aristotle as an individual seems almost comically small when compared to Plato. Aristotle is a cheerful optimist who ultimately believes in nothing: he can write scientific tracts about the nature of gods or God just as easily as about the weather, or about how to write speeches, and really to him the topic of the discussion is of no particular importance. Plato’s life and writing are haunted by tragedy, the shadow of his larger-than-life teacher, for whose death he could never bring himself to forgive the world. There was never any such person in Aristotle’s life — only Plato himself, wealthy and idle, who never quite crossed that same line of sacrificing himself for philosophy. Thus, for all that Aristotle may have made short work of Plato’s theory logically, this does absolutely nothing to diminish the deep, pained grief that gives weight to Plato’s deliberately obfuscated world of ideas:

‘They say, my friend,’ Socrates continued, ‘that, first of all, this earth, seen from above, resembles a twelve-sided leather ball, painted with colours like those used by painters; only there the whole earth consists of similar and even more beautiful and pure colours. There a part of it is purple, of amazing beauty, another part is golden, and another is whiter than plaster or snow. It also has other colours, in much greater quantity and far superior to what we see. And even the very hollows of it, full of water and air, gleam with an array of colours, so that the unity of its appearance shows uninterrupted diversity.
If the earth is like this, then so are the plants, that is, the trees, flowers and fruits; so are the mountains, so are the stones themselves in their smoothness, transparency and perfect colour, and their parts are exactly those stones that are so loved among us: cornelian, jasper, emerald and others like these. There is nothing there that would be worse than these; on the contrary, everything is much better — and the reason is that those stones are pure, undamaged and uncorroded, unlike those here, by decay, salt and everything that flows down here and communicates ugliness and disease to the stones, earth, animals and plants.’

from “Phaedo”

These words are spoken by Socrates just before his death — the last speech of the only human being whom Plato ever loved, resigned to his unjust sentence and already in some way removed from the world. Up to this point, the dialogue has been structured like a philosophical exchange, with logical arguments, but now, logic is silent. And indeed, Plato’s “proofs” of the immortality of the soul, which make up the bulk of “Phaedo,” start to seem silly and above all unnecessary next to the clarity and authority of this final vision.

(Continuation: part 3.)

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s